The public sphere habermas pdf


















Because potential topics of discussion are numerous, the public sphere may be divided into smaller and more cohesive conversations which focus on specific issues. A political public sphere holds public discourse about topics connected to governing and political practice. The Habermasian model of a public sphere holds a normative claim. That is, he describes a space which can only exist in an ideal democratic state, where equal participation and consideration are available to everyone.

This second point has even stronger application if the discourse in view involves philosophy, because philosophy is notorious for generating disagreement. In other disciplines such as history, physics or the biological sciences, convergence on truth secures consensus, and hypotheses that were once viable cease to be so, and recede into the history of the subject. Philosophy knows no such convergence. There are no philosophical doctrines that cannot come round again. This is why of all the rational discourses one might choose in order to arrive at an agreed political consensus, philosophy appears the least well suited.

Consequently, if the need for agreement is paramount, and if the use of force will secure this while engagement in philosophy will not, there is every reason to prefer force. In summary, the model of discourse ethics as the structure of the public sphere that will convert it from a sphere of unstructured conversational exchange to a sphere of public reason makes that sphere both anti-democratic and ineffectual.

The former flaw we could live with, but the latter we could not. In order to see this, it is worth remembering that the primary role of the concept of discourse ethics is in morality, not politics. Its purpose is to show how, in the absence of demonstrable universal norms, morality need not fall prey to either skepticism or cultural relativism.

In the context of moral theory, it is the possibility not the fact of agreement that is crucial. But the role it must have in the public sphere is quite different. The legitimation of political action through consensus can only be accomplished by actual agreement. Hypothetical consent is not enough. We are free to declare that those who will not abide by the rules of discourse ethics -- racists, for instance -- have renounced their entitlement to be considered serious contributors to moral debate.

It is quite a different matter to declare that they have no claim to citizenship. Its purpose is to lay down conditions for participation in public discussion that will make the outcome of such discussion capable of justifying political coercion, and this purpose is unmistakably consonant with the idea of a public sphere. Our exercise of political power is proper and hence justifiable only when it is exercised in accordance with a constitution the essentials of which all citizens may reasonably be expected to endorse in the light of principles and ideals acceptable to them as reasonable and rational.

Rawls This assertion is importantly from a very similar one — namely the view that the exercise of political power is proper and hence justifiable when it is in accordance with a constitution the essentials of which are reasonable and rational. Between constitutional provisions and what is reasonable and rational, Rawls places endorsement on the part of citizens. This is why some conception of public reason is required, and with it some concept of the public sphere.

The picture is in sharp contrast to, for instance, a straightforward appeal to natural law or human rights as tests for the validity of constitutional provisions. IV The position we have reached is this.

A widely held conception thinks of the political structure of modern societies as having three levels or perhaps comprising three interlocking circles. One level is made up of the ruling class that governs and a another of private individuals subject to that government. In between is a mediating public sphere, open to all citizens and constituted by an uncoerced exchange of information and ideas.

It is in this public sphere that government is subjected to the tribunal of public opinion. Political actions must pass this test if they are to be exercises in rational authority rather than arbitrarily imposed dictates.

The picture is a plausible and influential one, but closer examination reveals that the crucial connection with rationality is impossible to sustain. Either the test is public opinion, in which case it is of no consequence how it is arrived at, or the test is rational scrutiny, in which case the mere opinions of citizens as revealed opinion polls and the like should be ignored.

The additional elements in both Habermas and Rawls that might be called upon to address this difficulty — discourse ethics and public reason — which at first sight offer the possibility of construing the public sphere as itself a sphere of reason, founder on essentially the same dichotomy; either political consensus is what we ought to have in view, in which case coercion might be far more effective at securing it, or it is rational justification, in which case what citizens actually agree about is irrelevant.

Its role, and significance, depends upon some such concept as the public sphere. If the public sphere is fundamentally unstable — threatened by popular democracy on the one side and the authority of reason on the other — there can be no role for political philosophy of the recommending sort, whose ambition precisely is to be a rationally authoritative contributor to debates in that sphere. The most it can be is one more voice in the political cacophony of voices.

And given its distinctive character as a mode of thought that typically raises critical questions rather than producing definitive answers in which intellectual opinion converges, it is more likely to intensify the cacophony than generate rational harmony. What then, is political philosophy to do? The answer is to content itself with the Hegelian dictum that the owl of Minerva takes its flight at dusk. Philosophical reflection applied to politics is no different to philosophical reflection applied to anything else.

In other words, autonomy, social cooperation and mutuality are deemed to be features of unencumbered anthropological communicative reason which is in turn an enabling condition for democratic reasoned argumentation — a precondition for democracy.

Theory thus already presupposes what it tries to demonstrate analytically and achieve politically. When democracy and its attendant rational and sociable subjects becomes both a normative ideal and a component of the ontology, the ensuing circularity forecloses the critical enterprise. Democracy as an ideal and an enabling condition for attaining this ideal becomes immune to critical scrutiny -- democracy becomes an idol.

This risks making the enterprise of the critique of ideology complicit in moral and ideological justifications for that social order whose injustices and contradictions are meant to form the object of critique. In other words, the democratic turn in Critical Theory has not only deserted the critique of capitalism as an organizing pillar of social criticism.

Enters Ideologiekritik-cum-ideology- construction. Once democracy is equated with the emancipatory project itself, the concept can no longer perform the aporetic work of disclosure. In the context of the early twenty-first century — a time beset by the rise of autocrats professing to salvage democracy -- the challenge is to keep our faith in democracy without elevating it to an idol. To stay the course between dogmatism and scepticism, democratic theory needs to preserve the contestability of its core concept — that of democracy -- and deploy it in the aporetic project of critique.

This contestability, I have suggested, is not just a matter of maintaining the definitional openness, or indeterminacy, of the notion of democracy. Rather, it consists in on-going scrutiny of the work this notion does in view of the goals of emancipation.

In order to leave the space of reflexive contestation open, a distance needs to be maintained between the normative goals of theory, the social ontology from which theorising proceeds, and the requisite tools of analysis.

When these are equated, the ensuing circularity vitiates the rigor of the analysis: in this mode, a theory can do little more than supply normative validation of its object of analysis, thereby becoming a vehicle of ideology construction. Enhancing in this way its own credentials, democratic theory is prone to operate in the manner of a political theology committed to the fostering of democracy as a civil religion. If this is the aspiration of democratic political theory — then we know what road to take.

Such a critical effort cannot only seek to disclose the ways in which capitalism imperils democracy, but must also clarify the ways in which liberal democracy as a political system hampers or enables capitalism as a social system.

To the extent that democratic politics concerns institutionally mediated expressions of broadly shared preferences, democracy as a political system functions on the terrain of socially produced subjectivities. The dynamics of capital reproduction affect, even if they do not constitute, the democratic subjects.

It is in this way that liberal democracy becomes not only hostage to the exploitative dynamic of capitalism but also complicit in these dynamics. Even in conditions of fully democratised capitalism, when the structures of private property of the means of production and the attendant asymmetries of power are eliminated, democratic citizens can remain fully committed to the process of capital reproduction with all its deleterious effects on human beings, their societies and their natural environment.

That we are all equally complicit in, and equally damaged by, these dynamics is not much of a consolation. This means that political theory should remain committed to the normative ideals of democracy without burdening democratic politics of inclusion and equality with the task of radical social transformation. If it is to discern the path for such a transformation towards a more just society, critical political theory should aim to develop as a sociologically informed critique of the historically specific social order we inhabit.

For truly democratic politics demands a truly democratic society. A reader, London: Routledge, pp. Allen, Amy : Emancipation without utopia. Subjection, modernity, and the normative claims of feminist critical theory, in: Hypatia 30 3 , pp. Allen, Amy : The end of progress. Azmanova, Albena : Critical theory.

Azmanova, Albena : Empowerment as surrender. How women lost the battle for emancipation as they won equality and inclusion, in: Social Research 83 3 , pp. Azmanova, Albena : Relational, structural and systemic forms of power. Novum organum scientiarum, Cambridge University Press. Billig, Michel : Ideology and opinions. Studies in rhetorical psychology, London: Sage Publications. Calhoun, Craig : Introduction.

Habermas and the public sphere, in: Calhoun, Craig Ed. Cook, Deborah : Critical stratagems in Adorno and Habermas. Theories of ideology and the ideology of theory, in: Historical Materialism 6, pp. Grammaire, Saskatoon: HardPress, Engels, Frederick []. Habermas contra Adorno, in: Historical Materialism 11 2 , pp. Does democracy still enjoy an epistemic dimension?

The impact of normative theory on empirical research, in: Communication Theory 16 4 , pp. Horkheimer, Max. New York: Continuum, Marx, Karl [] : Capital. A critique of political economy, 3 vols, vol. One trenchant critique of the Habermasian public sphere conception, voiced particularly strongly by poststructuralist-influenced critics, is that it fails to fully account for exclusion. In this … Expand. Social Science History. Since , Jurgen Habermas has turned increasingly toward questions on the role of religion in the public sphere.

Modifying his earlier position, Habermas now argues for the equal inclusion of … Expand. Public sphere in Latin America: a map of the historiography. Some historians have used it as a model to fit … Expand. What is a medium? Sociology, Political Science. This essay discusses anthropological approaches to the study of media interacting with contexts of ethnic and religious diversity. The main argument is that not only issues of access to and exclusion … Expand.

View 2 excerpts, cites background.



0コメント

  • 1000 / 1000